公共支出纯理论Paul A. Samuelson英文原著及中文翻译

THE PURE THEORY OF PUBLIC EXPENDITURE
Paul A. Samuelson
1. Assumptions.  Except for Sax, Wicksell,Lindahl,  Musgrave, and  Bowen, economists have rather neglected the theory of optimal public expenditure, spending most of their energy on the theory of taxation.  Therefore, I explicitly assume two categories of goods: ordinary private consumption goods which can be parcelled out among different individualsaccording to the relations and collective consumption goods which all enjoy in common in the sense that each individual's consumption of such a good leads to no subtraction from any other individual's consumption of that good, so that simultaneously for each and every th individual and each collective consumptive good.  I assume no mystical collective mind that enjoys collective consumption goods; instead I assume each individual has a consistent set of ordinal preferences with respect to his consumption of all goods (collective as well as private) which can be summarized by a regularly smooth and convex utility index (any monotonic stretching of the utility index is of course also an admissible cardinal index of preference). I shall throughout follo
w the convention of writing the partial derivative of any function with respect to its th argument by a subscript, so that etc.  Provided economic quantities can be divided into two groups, (1) outputs or goods which everyone always wants to maximize and (2) inputs or factors which everyone always wants to minimize, we are free to change the algebraic signs of the latter category and from then on to work only with "goods," knowing that the case of factor inputs is covered as well. Hence by this convention we are sure that always.
To keep production assumptions at the minimum level of simplicity, I assume a regularly convex and smooth production-possibility schedule relating totals of all outputs, private and collective; or, with 、and ratios determinate and subject to the generalized laws of diminishing returns.
Feasibility considerations disregarded, there is a maximal (ordinal) utility frontier representing the Pareto-optimal points—of which there  are  an  (swww.902007—I) fold infinitywith the property that from such a frontier point you can make one person better off only by making some other person worse off. If we wish to make normative judgments concerning the relative ethical desirability of different configurations involving some individuals being on a higher level of indifference and some on a lower, we must be presented with a set of ordinal interpersonal norms or with a social welfare function representing a consistent set of ethical preferences among all the possible states of the system. It is not a "scientific" task of the economist to "deduce" the form of this function; this can have as many forms as there are possible ethical views; for the present purpose, the only restriction placed on the social welfare function is that it shall always increase or decrease when any one person's ordinal preference increases or decreases, all others staying on their same indifference levels: mathematically, we narrow it to the class that any one of its indexes can be written with .
2. Optimal Conditions.  In terms of these周涵 成都书店 norms, there is a "best state of the world" which
is defined mathematically in simple regular cases by the marginal conditions
  or   (1)
or         (2)    or   (3)
Equations (黎曼函数1) and (3) are essentially those given in the chapter on welfare economics in my Foundations of Economic Analysis. They constitute my version of the "new welfare economics." Alone (1) represents that subset of relations which  defines the Pareto-optimal utility frontier and which by itself represents what I regard as the unnecessarily narrow version of what once was called the "new welfare economics."
The new element added here is the set (2), which constitutes a pure theory of government expenditure on collective consumption goods. By themselves(1)and (2)define the (sΙ) fold infinity of  utility frontier points; only木板削削when a set of interpersonal n
ormative conditions equivalent to  (3)  is supplied are we able to define an unambiguously "best" state.
Since formulating the conditions (2)some years ago, I have learned from the published and unpublished writings of Richard Musgrave that their essential logic is contained in the "voluntary-exchange" theories of public finance of the  Sax-Wicksell-Lindahl-Musgrave type, and I have also noted Howard Bowen's independent discovery of them in Bowen's writings of a decade ago. A graphical interpretation of 十一届三中全会的意义these conditions in terms of vertical rather than horizontal  addition  of  different  individuals' marginal-rate-of-substitution schedules can be given; but what I must emphasize is that there is a different such schedule for each individual at each of the (sΙ)fold infinity of different distributions of relative welfare along the utility frontier.
3.  Impossibility of decentralized spontaneous solution. So much for the involved optimizing equations that an omniscient calculating machine could theoretically solve if fed the postulated functions. No such machine now exists. But it is well known that an "analogue calculating machine" can be provided by competitive market pricing, (a) so long as the production functions satisfy the neoclassical assumptions of constant returns to scale and generalized diminishing returns and (b) so long as the individuals' indifference contours have regular convexity and, we may add, (c) so long as all goods are private. We can then insert between the right- and left-hand sides of (Ι) the equality with uniform market prices and adjoin the budget equations for each individual
                            (1)1
全国人民代表大会设立民族委员会where L' is a lump-sum tax for each individual so selected in algebraic value as to lead to the "best" state of the world. Now note, if there were no collective consumption goods, then (Ι) and (r)‘can have their solution enormously simplified. Why?  Because on the one hand perfect competition among productive enterprises would ensure that goods are produced at minimum costs and are sold at proper marginal costs, with all factors receiving their proper marginal productivities; and on the other hand, each individual, in seeking as a competitive buyer to get to the highest level of indifference subject to given prices and tax, would be led as if by an Invisible Hand to the grand solution of the social maximum position. Of course the institutional framework of competition would have to be maintained, and political decision making would still be necessary, but of a computationally minimum type, namely, algebraic taxes and transfers would have to be varied until society is swung to the ethical observer's optimum. The servant of the ethical observer would not have to make explicit decisions about each. person's detailed consumption and work; he need only decide about generalized purchasing power, knowing that each person can be counted on to allocate it optimally. In
terms of communication theory and game terminology, each person is motivated to do the signalling of his tastes needed to define and reach the attainable-bliss point.

本文发布于:2024-09-21 05:44:35,感谢您对本站的认可!

本文链接:https://www.17tex.com/xueshu/106617.html

版权声明:本站内容均来自互联网,仅供演示用,请勿用于商业和其他非法用途。如果侵犯了您的权益请与我们联系,我们将在24小时内删除。

上一篇:墨菲定律原理
下一篇:国际财政
标签:成都   木板   书店   削削
留言与评论(共有 0 条评论)
   
验证码:
Copyright ©2019-2024 Comsenz Inc.Powered by © 易纺专利技术学习网 豫ICP备2022007602号 豫公网安备41160202000603 站长QQ:729038198 关于我们 投诉建议